Today's Medical Humanities Bookworm reviews Survival of the Sickest by Dr. Sharon Moalem with Jonathan Prince.
Moalem has a Ph.D in human physiology with a focus on neurogenetics and human evolution, and is currently finishing medical school at Mount Sinai College of Medicine in New York City.
Oversimplified, Moalem's thesis is that many diseases, especially chronic ones, may continue to exist in the gene pool because they supplied our ancestors with evolutionary advantages. This is unremarkable. It has been known for quite some time, for example, that sickle cell trait confers resistance to malaria, which is one reason why persons of African descent are virtually the exclusive carriers of sickle cell trait.
But Moalem goes much further, and argues that many diseases that had not been understood in the context of reproductive fitness actually did confer an evolutionary advantage, such as hemochromatosis, plague, and juvenile diabetes. Much of the book is devoted to explanation of how these diseases did confer such advantages.
Moalem goes further, however, in drawing on the circular geometry of systems biology (the feedback loop model being one of the most common and useful metaphors), and reasons that it is important not to overlook the ways in which human activities have prompted evolutionary changes, as well. Extreme virulence tends not to confer evolutionary advantages on microbes simply because the human host may die too quickly, before the microorganisms have a chance to secure a new host. This is one reason why microbes that have some of the longest histories of human infection have evolved to exist in relative stability with the human host.
One example of this is bacteria in the gut, and an even more extreme example of this may be mitochondria, which are descendants of ancient bacteria that evolved to become a crucial part of human cell biology. Moalem cites some of the ideas of biologist Paul Ewald to argue that we should consider entirely new strategies of understanding disease, and that measures designed to prompt evolutionary changes in dangerous microbes may potentially be more effective than current forms of treatment. Unfortunately at least in the case of bacteria, our most common and effective means of treatment promotes increased virulence by way of drug-resistance. Ewald, and Moalem, suggests that perhaps we can harness this relationship in our favor.
All in all, I liked the book, though I did have several reservations. The first is the "evolutionaziation" of social phenomena, which might be analgous to medicalization. That is to say, it is axiomatic in the medical humanities that illness is experienced socially, and that seeing such experiences solely via the clinical gaze is reductionist and transforms the provider into a technician who merely treats the disease, as opposed to healing the patient. There is a similar danger, IMO, in seeing illness solely in the context of evolutionary advantage. This is not deny the significance of evolution in our understanding of pathology and disease, but simply to suggest that there may be a tendency to grant far too much explanatory power to evolutionary theory. The extension of such theory into domains in which other modalities may reveal much more of human and ethical significance is the very definition of scientism.
This is not to accuse Moalem and Prince of outright scientism, especially because Moalem's personal story of how he became interested in these problems -- in light of his grandfather's illness -- is heartfelt and touching. Moalem and Prince understand the significance of the intersubjective and social elements of illness, but I would have preferred much more focus on these issues than on evolutionary paradigms. But, I am a medical humanist in-training, so I suppose such a response from me would hardly be unexpected.
If I am wary of the tendency to seek to explain so much of health and illness in context of evolutionary theory, I am frequently dismayed by the ways in which genes are portrayed. Contrary to what many believe, genes themselves explain little of human health and illness, because genes exist only in a nonlinear dynamical system in which countless attractors and influences (including other genes) work in integrated and complex ways to produce overall system behavior.
In short, as Evelyn Fox Keller reminds, gene action is far more interesting than genes themselves, because what we should like to know, IMO, is how genes work to produce actual effects. And this is an infinitely more complicated question than deciphering genetic information in and of itself, which is partly why the Human Genome Project, as important as it clearly is, has not yet revolutionized human existence.
I did enjoy the book, and Moalem's perspective is certainly intriguing.