Today's entry in the Medical Humanities Lexicon is "theodicy."
I believe in the sun even when it is not shining.
I believe in love even when feeling it not.
I believe in God even when he was silent.
This refrain was inscribed on the wall of a cellar in Cologne, Germany where Jews hid from the Nazis. It was found by Allied troops in 1945. Aside from its stark beauty, it neatly encapsulates the problem of theodicy, which is roughly defined as the question of how God can be perceived as good, right, or just, given the existence of suffering and evil in the world.
The problem arises as a dilemma in the technical sense. Given the phenomena of evil, there are apparently two possibilities: either God is incapable of preventing the evil in question, or God is capable of preventing that evil but chooses not to do so. The first option seems unsatisfying because it denies omnipotence to God, which is deeply problematic at least for many who ascribe Judeo-Christian beliefs. The second option is arguably worse because it problematizes the notion of a just, benevolent God; how could such a God choose to permit such evil to occur? How could God be silent in the face of such suffering?
The problem of theodicy, which is sometimes referred to as the ontological problem of evil, is at least as old in Judeo-Christian traditions as the Book of Job itself, which is a marvelous albeit deeply troubling work. To provide a basic narrative, Job is a righteous person who has generally enjoyed good health and prosperity. Suddenly, and for no apparent reason, a number of horrific calamities befall him. He loses all of his money, his children die one by one, he becomes afflicted with a number of gruesome illnesses, etc. He naturally begins to wonder why his life has taken such a sharp turn, especially given that he has generally lived a life of piety. This last point is important, for it is no answer to Job's problems to assert that his current misfortunes are his just desert, for there is no suggestion anywhere in the text that Job has perpetrated any works that would merit such punishment.
Job's problem, of course, is the problem of theodicy: the innocent suffer. How can God justify it? How can God be both all-powerful and benevolent if the innocent suffer? The remainder of the text consists generally of a dialogue between Job and his peers, who assert the point I have already suggested is unpersuasive: Job's misfortunes must be linked to his own sins. The idea that suffering is linked to personal sin is pervasive, especially in Judeo-Christian morality, and, in On the Geneology of Morals, Nietzsche provides the most eloquent explanation for why this idea maintains such currency: “[t]he meaninglessness of suffering, not suffering itself, was the curse that lay over mankind so far . . . .” (162) The sin-suffering narrative is so powerful precisely because it engenders meaning in the face of suffering, which may be more tolerable than the idea that suffering is entirely arbitrary:
suffering was interpreted; the tremendous void seemed to have been filled; the door was closed to any kind of suicidal nihilism . . . it placed all suffering in the perspective of guilt. But all this notwithstanding -- man was saved thereby, he possessed a meaning; he was henceforth no longer like a leaf in the wind.
Ibid.
Job, however, rejects this narrative. He insists that he is blameless, though his peers repeatedly return to the sin-suffering link both to explain Job's misfortunes and to preserve the notions of an omnipotent benevolent God. In chapter 21 of the Book, Job moves to preseve the notion of a just God at the expense of the notion of an omnipotent God. He argues not that God rules the world unjustly, but that he does not "rule" it all. In a conception that presages the Deist ethos, the world just runs on without divine control.
God eventually appears, but one of the most fascinating puzzles of the entire Book is that God never answers the problem of theodicy. Rather, God points out the immense chasm separating human and divine knowledge, and implies that he is uniquely concerned with the plight of humanity. But he never provides a resolution to the dilemma. Interestingly, Job is utterly satisfied with this response. Some exegetes have interpreted this climax as signfying Job's relief at the presence of God. God is no longer silent, to return to our original quotation. His presence alone soothes Job, even if he supplies no answer to the problem that has been causing Job such anguish.
The paradox here is rather profound. While Job may be soothed by being close to God, he could not be farther from divine understanding, as God himself reminds Job. Many Jewish thinkers have attempted to resolve this paradox in one of two principal ways: (1) tracking Job's reaction, some commentators, most notably Maimonides have accepted the epistemic gap between human and divine comprehension, but have argued that suffering may be transcended through closer relation to the divine presence itself; or (2) some commentators, especially 20th century thinkers, have adopted Job's earlier tack, and begun to reject the notion of an omnipotent deity.
Maimonides, roughly contemporary of Aquinas, was arguably just as enamored with the concept of right reason as was the latter. He suggested that through our intellect we could transcend our material existence and the suffering that accompanied it and move closer to God. Though I admit to finding the transcendentalist response deeply unsatisfying, one arguably redeeming feature of the Maimonidean version is that it places the onus on humans to work out the problem of theodicy. According to Maimonides, we cannot expect God to solve this problem for us. It is humans who must grapple with it. This response to me sounds remarkably familiar to one of my favorite essays ever, one which holds great personal significance for me, Camus' Myth of Sisyphus. It is Sisyphus who choose his own fate by pushing the boulder up the hill. Il faut imaginer Sisyphe heureux.
While transcendentalism maintained a powerful hold in Judeo-Christian thought for centuries following Maimonides, it became increasingly difficult to stomach after the Shoah. Richard Rubenstein argues that "[t]he fact of Auschwitz rules out such ideas forever" (Leaman 187). Moreover, the notion of a God who is utterly detached from the suffering of his children is deeply problematic for a tradition built upon the negation of that notion. Harold Kushner, in his well-known account of his attempts to make meaning of the death of his son, escapes the theodic dilemma by rejecting God's omnipotence. He observes that he can worship a benevolent but not all-powerful God, but that he cannot worship an omnipotent being who allows the innocent to suffer so. Elie Wiesel adopts an entirely pragmatic approach: to abandon God would be to grant success to the hopes of the Nazis in seeking to exterminate a Jewish way of living and thinking. Thus, belief in God is a pragmatic course, though he does not offer any resolution to the problem of theodicy itself.
Finally, Leibniz proposed that this world, even with its significant evils, is the best of all possible worlds. Under this analysis, all actual evils are essential ingredients in the divine plan in which this world remains the best of all possible worlds. To omit these evils would wreck the entire design itself. Numerous commentators have criticized this proposal on many different grounds, the most obvious of which is that it seems to rely on a brazenly consequentialist ethic.
It should take no great exercise of moral imagination to see the connection of the problem of theodicy to the medical humanities. The question of how an omnipotent, benevolent God can permit the innocent to suffer remains a profound problem for many, both for providers and health care professionals, and for patients and caregivers (each of whom may well take on both kinds of roles in their lives on multiple occasions). Of course, the problem of theodicy is no problem at all for atheists, and there are certainly non-Western belief systems which are untroubled by the problem because the relevant deity or deities is not deemed omnipotent to begin with.
Nevertheless, I submit it is safe to suggest that there are many participants in medical practice for whom the problem of theodicy is profound and agonizing. Even outside of a Western religious paradigm, Eric Cassell, one of the chief authorities on suffering, states that "[t]ranscendence is probably the most powerful way in which one is restored to wholeness after an injury to personhood" (45).
And even for those untroubled by the problem of theodicy, the sin-suffering narrative has demonstable clinical effects. Some patients, for example, do not request adequate pain management because they feel that the pain is their just desert for the sins they have committed. Through their suffering, they hope to expiate their sins. Susan Sontag's Illness as Metaphor highlights some of the ways in which the suffering of cancer patients is linked to sin. Saul Brody's seminal work on the history of leprosy shows an even closer link between illness, suffering, and sin. Arguably, part of the impetus for such a narrative is that it resolves the problem of theodicy. If suffering is linked to merit, or lack thereof, the notion of an omnipotent, benevolent God is left untroubled.
Thoughts?
____________________________________________________________
Bibliography
Mitchell, Stephen, trans. The Book of Job. New York: HarperPerennial Press, 1987.
The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, 2d ed., s.v., "Theodicy."
Leaman, Oliver. Evil and Suffering in Jewish Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Freeman, David L., Abrams, Judith Z., eds. Illness and Health in the Jewish Tradition. Philadelphia: The Jewish Publication Society, 1999.
Kinzbrunner, Barry. "Jewish Medical Ethics and End-of-Life Care." Journal of Palliative Medicine 7, no. 4 (2004): 567.
Barilan, Y. Michael. "Revisiting the Problem of Jewish Bioethics: The Case of Terminal Care." Journal of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics 13, no. 2 (2003): 147.
Cassell, Eric J. The Nature of Suffering and the Goals of Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
Kushner, Harold. When Bad Things Happen to Good People. New York: Avon Press, 1981.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Geneology of Morals. Translated by Walter Kauffman & RJ Hollingdale. New York: Random House, 1989.
Kapeli, Silvia. "Between Suffering and Redemption: Religious Motives in Jewish and Christian Cancer Patients' Coping." Scandinavian Journal of Caring Sciences 14, no. 2 (2000): 85.
Gunderman, Richard B. "Medicine and the Question of Suffering." Second Opinion 14, no. 1 (1990): 16.
Rahula, Walpola. What the Buddha Taught. New York: Grove Press, 1974.
Sontag, Susan. Illness as Metaphor and AIDS and its Metaphors. New York: Picador Press, 1989.
Brody, Saul. The Disease of the Soul: Leprosy in Medieval Literature. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1974.